Welcome
to this discussion on philosophy and the social sciences. Our focus in this post
will be on philosophy’s relationship with the social sciences in order to
ascertain the soundness of the assumptions and claims made in this area of
study.
To
achieve this, we shall discuss this topic under three sub-headings:
1.
The Notion of the Social Sciences
2.
Philosophy and the Social Sciences
3.
Critical Theory.
If,
as emphasized in the last article, philosophy’s role in the physical sciences is crucial, perhaps its interest in the
social sciences can be recognized as even greater. This is because, among other
things, the social sciences concern human beings who are less predictable than
the physical world and so should not be reduced to, or treated as purely
mechanical.
In
this article, you will have a clear understanding of what the social sciences
are, the sense in which the social sciences are sciences, the subject matter
and purpose of the social sciences and the relationship between philosophy and the
social sciences.
The Notion of Social Sciences
As pointed out earlier, if science is an organized body of systematic knowledge, then the social sciences would also qualify as science.
The distinction between
the social sciences and the natural or physical sciences would therefore lie in
what constitutes their subject matter, for while the natural sciences study the
physical world, the social sciences study human beings and their social
environment.
And
since the human reality is not exclusively mechanistic, it cannot be reduced to
a set of physical attributes or activities which are susceptible to dependable
and unvarying measurement.
As
A. C. Bouquet observes, It may be questioned whether a world-view expressing
itself in a habitual attitude can be deduced from scientific enquiry as
commonly conceived. …the bodies of the sane man, the criminal, the lunatic, the
genius and the prophet, are all equally matter for scientific analysis, but a
world-view on a purely scientific basis would seem to be impossible, unless by
science we mean more than physical science, and make it embrace an impartial
observation of human thought, with deductions therefrom.
The
social sciences became a significant branch of intellectual study during the
Enlightenment period. This is because it was an offshoot of the clamor for
human interests and emancipation that characterized the new mode of thinking in
the Enlightenment age.
At
its inception, the social science was greatly inspired by the logical
positivists' position that the empirical method affects a perfect and objective
study of all phenomena including the human person and the overall society in
which he exists.
Social
science therefore developed as a result of this new tendency and the underlying
presumption that the scientific tool is appropriate and adequate for every
intellectual project. The social sciences refer to those disciplines that study
human society and institutions as well as the relationship of individual
members within society.
In
other words, it is the science of social phenomena, whose focus is the social
aspects of human experience. It is the aspect of human knowledge which attempts
to understand general human behaviour in terms of his social, psychological and
perhaps his economic environment, in order to be able to describe and explain
such behaviours and as well as to also be able to predict such social
phenomena, given certain conditions.
Such
disciplines include Sociology, Psychology, Anthropology, Geography, Economics,
Political Science, and History.
The
social sciences, therefore, differ from the natural science in several
significant ways, one of which is in the application of the scientific method
described in the last unit.
John
Stuart Mill argues that in the social sciences the subject matter is too
complex to apply the normal methods of experiment.
And
Sodipo would further say: The more imaginative social scientist is of course
aware that the application of the methods and the conceptual categories of the
natural sciences, the employment of their ideas of causation, measurement, etc.
to the study of society is problematic, and he is exercised by that problem.
He
therefore realizes that there are social situations where what is needed for
understanding is not a sophisticated and very complicated mathematical model
but a conceptual framework in which sympathetic intuition and imaginative insight
would play a crucial role.
The
distinction between the natural and social sciences is also easily seen in the
area of causality and prediction.
Causal connections are not as readily
established in the social science as in the natural sciences, and therefore
predictions are less reliable in the former than in the latter.
For
example, combining hydrogen with oxygen in the right amount gives water.
In
this example, the combination of hydrogen and oxygen is the cause of water, and
it is predictable that, whenever this combination is done in the right
proportion, the resultant substance is always water. But in the case of human
behaviour, even though there are degrees of probability, it is practically
impossible to posit that, for every combination of factors, the results or
consequences are definite and invariable.
At
the same time, the observation of certain phenomena does not necessarily lead
to conclusions that cannot vary in any way. As a very simple example, it would
be unrealistic to say that, whenever an individual is observed as smiling or
laughing, such an individual is happy.
This
distinction is based on the fact that human beings and their actions are not as
predictable as the behaviour of elements in nature.
Martin
Hollis illustrates this when he argues that, if Africa suddenly becomes much
colder, a whole lot of things will change, and that the social effects of this
will not be as predictable as the natural effects, because a lot of human
variables will intervene in determining what the social effects would be, for
individuals as well as communities.
Alex
Rosenberg expresses the same issue more theoretically when he asks whether
human action can be explained in the way that natural science explains
phenomena in its domain:
If
the answer is yes, why are our explanations of human action so much less
precise and the predictions based on them so much weaker than explanations in
natural science?
If
the answer is no, what is the right way to explain action scientifically?
If
there is no adequate scientific explanation of human actions, as some
philosophers and social scientists claim:
Why
does human action require an approach different from that of natural science,
and what approach is required?
In
its quest for an acceptable explanatory model, the social sciences employ the
scientific method in their investigations so as to achieve the following
objectives:
1.
Understanding and making more intelligible the behaviour, particularly the social
behaviour, of human beings.
2.
Establishing the governing laws behind most human behavior.
3.
Understanding the history of human development, in order to predict in the face
of given laws, the future behaviour of man.
4.
Guiding the behaviour of human beings in a socially desirable way.
The
extent to which they are able to achieve these goals is a different issue
altogether.
At
best, one can say that the social sciences offer functional explanations of
social phenomena.
A
functional explanation of a social feature, according to Daniel E. Little, “is
one that explains the presence and persistence of the feature in terms of the
beneficial consequences the feature has for the on-going working of the social
system as a whole.”
Also read: Philosophy and Religion
Philosophy and the Social Sciences
Philosophy’s
relationship with the social sciences is based on the former’s role in the
analysis and critique of other disciplines.
Philosophy
of the social sciences, just like the philosophy of science, is out to study
the various goals and methods of the social science, with the aim of evaluating
whether the discipline is able to live up to the expectation of humanity.
Philosophy
of the social sciences ponders on certain issues inherited from the philosophy
of natural science and also reflects on problems and issues generated by its
own peculiar disciplinary orientation. For example, this area of philosophy
reacts to the question of the appropriate methodology for the social scientific
enterprise, which is an age long problem in philosophy of natural science.
As
R.S Rudner says in his Philosophy of Social Science, "the philosopher of
social science is ranged with the philosopher of science in that both focus
their attention on problems of methodology.
Some
of the central problems that philosophers of the social sciences address
include:
(1)
The extent to which one can say that human social life which the social
sciences claim to study is, or is not similar to non-human nature which is
studied by the natural science
(2) The extent to which human and social experiences can be explainable by using the scientific method
(3) The extent to which the results and findings of the
social scientists can be used to predict and control future occurrences in the
social world in the same way in which findings in the natural sciences are used
to predict and control occurrences in the natural world
(4)
The extent of to which the themes, logic and the method of the social science
are distinctively peculiar as basis for differentiating the social science from
the humanities and for associating the social science with the natural science
(5)
The extent to which we can reduce human actions to scientific paradigm which is
capable of fulfilling the four goals of science, described by Keith Webb as
prediction, explanation, control, and understanding.
While
describing the philosophy of the social sciences as the study of the logic and
methods of the social sciences, Daniel E. Little goes on to discuss the central
questions in the philosophy of the social sciences, questions similar to those
enumerated in the last paragraph:
What
are the criteria of a good social explanation?
How
(if at all) are the social sciences distinct from the natural sciences?
Is
there a distinctive method for social research?
Through
what empirical procedures are social science assertions to be evaluated?
Are
there irreducible social laws?
Are
there causal relations among social phenomena?
Do
social facts and regularities require some form of reduction to facts about
individuals?
What
is the role of theory in social explanation?
The
philosophy of social science aims to provide an interpretation of the social
sciences that answers these questions.
Discussing
further the main concerns of philosophy of the social science, Alex Rosenberg
explains that being clear about a discipline's philosophy is essential because
at the frontiers of the disciplines….the unavoidability and importance of
philosophical questions are even more significant for the social scientist than
for the natural scientist.”
He goes on to explain that the only source of guidance for research in the social sciences must come from philosophical theories.
“In the end,” he says, “the
philosophy of social science is not only inevitable and unavoidable for social
scientists, but it must also be shaped by them as much as by philosophers.”
One
major aspect of the relationship between philosophy and social science is that,
while social science tries to make sense of social events and data, philosophy,
as it were, tries to make sense of the sense which social science is making of
social events. Philosophy interrogates the social sciences with the aim of
understanding and clarifying, in general terms, the methods, claims and
assumptions of the latter.
For
example, even though the social sciences attempt to collect data and reach
conclusions on what accounts for such human values as good, happiness, right,
and so on, properly defining those notions in themselves is the function of
philosophy.
Also read: Philosophy as a Second-Order Activity
Critical theory
A
good example of philosophy’s role in the social sciences is seen in the
commitment of the Frankfurt School to the ‘critical theory of society’.
According
to James Bonham, critical theory is “any social theory that is at the same time
explanatory, normative, practical, and self-reflexive.”
He also observes: Critical theory is primarily a way of doing philosophy, integrating the normative aspects of philosophical reflection with the explanatory achievements of the social sciences.
The ultimate goal of its
program is to link theory and practice, to provide insight, and to empower
subjects to change their oppressive circumstances and achieve human
emancipation, a rational society that satisfies human needs and powers.
Max
Horkheimer, a philosopher of social science and a member of the Frankfurt
School, wrote essays that focus on the relation of philosophy and social
science.
Besides
providing a clear definition and programme for critical social science, he
proposes that the normative orientation of philosophy should be combined with
the empirical research in the social sciences.
His
programmatic essays on the relation of philosophy and the social sciences long
provided the philosophical basis for Frankfurt School social criticism.
For
him, critical theory aims at emancipating human beings rather than merely
describing reality as it is now.
Read on: Political Philosophy and Social Engineering
Conclusion on Philosophy and
the Social Sciences
The
social sciences also lay claim to being ‘science’ based on their use of the
method of science. But unlike the latter, the social sciences that deal with
human behaviour within the context of man’s relationship with other humans in
society.
For
this reason, the social sciences deal with a subject matter that is not as
straightforward or as predictable as the physical sciences, a subject matter
that is much more complicated.
Thus,
using the scientific method to the extent that they are amenable, the social
sciences seek to better understand and explain the human being and his social
environment.
Philosophy’s
interest in the social sciences is to interrogate the method and logic of the
social sciences. We have examined the relationship between philosophy and the
social sciences in order to ascertain the soundness of the assumptions and
claims made in the social sciences.
To
the extent that science is described as an organized, systematic
Philosophy of the social
sciences attempts to examine this difference by critically assessing the
internal logic, assumptions, methodology and claims made in the social
sciences.
knowledge, the social
sciences also qualify as science, but since the social sciences deal with human
behaviour, they differ significantly from the natural or physical sciences.
Philosophy of the social
sciences attempts to examine this difference by critically assessing the
internal logic, assumptions, methodology and claims made in the social
sciences.
0 Comments