Religious pluralism is the state of being where every
individual in a religiously diverse society has the rights, freedoms, and
safety to worship, or not, according to their conscience. This definition
is founded in the American motto e pluribus unum, that we, as a nation, are
gathered together as one out of many.
Religious pluralism is an attitude or policy regarding the diversity of religious belief systems co-existing in society.
First, pluralism is not diversity alone, but
the energetic engagement with diversity. Diversity can and has meant the
creation of religious ghettoes with little traffic between or among them.
Today,
religious diversity is a given, but pluralism is not a given; it is an
achievement. Mere diversity without real encounter and relationship will yield
increasing tensions in our societies.
Second,
pluralism is not just tolerance, but the active seeking of understanding across
lines of difference. Tolerance is a necessary public virtue, but it does not
require Christians and Muslims, Hindus, Jews, and ardent secularists to know
anything about one another.
Tolerance
is too thin a foundation for a world of religious difference and proximity. It
does nothing to remove our ignorance of one another, and leaves in place the
stereotype, the half-truth, the fears that underlie old patterns of division
and violence.
In
the world in which we live today, our ignorance of one another will be
increasingly costly.
Third,
pluralism is not relativism, but the encounter of commitments. The new paradigm
of pluralism does not require us to leave our identities and our commitments
behind, for pluralism is the encounter of commitments.
It
means holding our deepest differences, even our religious differences, not in
isolation, but in relationship to one another.
Fourth,
pluralism is based on dialogue. The language of pluralism is that of dialogue
and encounter, give and take, criticism and self-criticism. Dialogue means both
speaking and listening, and that process reveals both common understandings and
real differences.
Dialogue
does not mean everyone at the “table” will agree with one another. Pluralism
involves the commitment to being at the table with one’s commitments.
In
this article you will be able to understand the critical issues that are
involved in the study of religion and interact more meaningfully on issues of
interfaith dialogue.
Religious Pluralism, Diversity and Tolerance
Religious
pluralism, to paraphrase the title of a recent academic work, goes beyond mere
toleration.
Beneke,
in Beyond Toleration: The Religious Origins of American Pluralism explains the
difference between religious tolerance and religious pluralism by pointing to
the situation in the late 18th century United States.
By
the 1730s, in most colonies religious minorities had obtained what
contemporaries called religious toleration: "The policy of toleration
relieved religious minorities of some physical punishments and some financial
burdens, but it did not make them free from the indignities of prejudice and
exclusion.
Nor
did it make them equal. Those 'tolerated' could still be barred from civil
offices, military positions, and university posts." This has happened in
many countries around the world.
In
short, religious toleration is only the absence of religious persecution, and
does not necessarily preclude religious discrimination. Religious pluralism can
be defined as "respecting the otherness of others" and accepting the
given uniqueness endowed to each one of us. Religious intolerance, defined as
the practice of keeping others from acting in accordance with their religious
beliefs, is not new.
However,
there is concern worldwide over the increasing amount, and increasingly violent
nature, of such behavior. Accordingly, there is understandably a renewed
interest in fostering religiously tolerant environments in which individuals
with differing religious perspectives can practice their faiths unencumbered.
A
number of philosophers have recently turned their attention to the relationship
between religious diversity and religious tolerance, with the main focus on
whether acknowledgement of, and subsequent reflection on, religious diversity
might lead to greater religious tolerance.
The
main argument supporting the claim that acknowledged diversity can foster
tolerance was proposed by the late Philip Quinn (Quinn, 2001, 57–80; 2002,
533–537; 2005a, 136–139). He maintained that:
(1)
Serious reflection on the undeniable reality of religious diversity will
necessarily weaken an individual's justification for believing that her
religious perspective is superior to the perspectives of others and that
(2)
this weakened justification can, and hopefully will for some, lead to greater
religious tolerance — for example, will lead to a more accepting, less
confrontational attitude toward others.
Both
of Quinn's contentions have been challenged. The claim that reflection of the
acknowledged reality of religious diversity reduces an individual's justified
confidence in the superiority of her position has been subject to at least two
types of criticism.
As noted earlier in our discussion of religious diversity and epistemic obligation, some philosophers agree with Alvin Plantinga that the proponent of a given religious perspective need not grant that his competitors are actually on equal epistemic footing and are thus justified in continuing to maintain that his perspective is superior without further reflection.
Other philosophers do not deny that proponents of differing religious perspectives are on equal epistemic footing or that reflection on these diversity perspectives might in some cases actually cause an individual to become less certain that her perspective is superior.
But they deny that there is any necessary epistemic connection between acknowledged diversity and a weakening of justified personal commitment. That is, they argue that a proponent of a given religious perspective can acknowledge both that those holding perspectives differ from hers are epistemic peers and that she is not in a position to demonstrate objectively that her position is superior and yet justifiably continue to maintain that her perspective is in fact superior.
Quinn's second contention that weakened justification in the superiority of one's perspective has the promising potential for fostering religious tolerance has also been challenged.
For
instance, William Lane Craig, Robert McKim, and Keith Yandell have all argued
recently that the weakening of a person's conviction that the specific
teachings of her religion, including the relevant moral teachings that prohibit
intolerance, are correct might in turn actually make it more likely that this
person will engage in intolerant behavior as it may well deflate the very
confidence in the relevant beliefs needed for inspiring tolerance.
Others,
such as William Hasker, have questioned whether Quinn's challenge to those who
hold firmly to the superiority of their religious perspectives that the reality
of religious diversity requires that they hold their perspectives less firmly will
have the effect Quinn intended.
It
was his hope that those challenged in this fashion would “soften” their exclusivist
convictions and thus be less likely to engage in intolerant behavior. But might
not just the opposite occur? Might not those told that the reality of religious
diversity reduces their justified confidence in their beliefs feel threatened
and thus, in an attempt to “stand up for the truth,” become even more
intolerant of those with other perspectives (Hasker, 2007)?
Those sympathetic to Quinn's position do not deny that some finding the justification for their religious beliefs challenged will respond defensively or that some coming to hold their religious beliefs less confidently might for that reason find themselves with a weaker basis for refraining from intolerant behavior.
But those sympathetic to Quinn's “pathway from diversity to tolerance” maintain
that acknowledged religious diversity can, and often does, foster in a person
(1)
A greater respect for her epistemic competitors and their positions
(2)
A more flexible, inclusive understanding of her own position, and that those
who respect their competitors and have a more inclusive understanding of their
own perspectives are less likely to engage in inappropriate intolerant
religious behavior.
7 Major Theories of the Origin of Religion
Interfaith Dialogue
Religious
pluralism is sometimes used as a synonym for interfaith dialogue. Interfaith
dialogue refers to dialogue between members of different religions for the goal
of reducing conflicts between their religions and to achieve agreed upon
mutually desirable goals.
Inter-religious
dialogue is difficult if the partners adopt a position of particularism, i.e.
if they only care about the concerns of their own group, but is favored by the
opposite attitude of universalism, where care is taken for the concerns of
others.
Interfaith
dialogue is easier if a religion's adherents have some form of inclusivism, the
belief that people in other religions may also have a way to salvation, even
though the fullness of salvation can be achieved only in one’s own religion.
Conversely,
believers with an exclusivist mindset will rather tend to proselytize followers
of other religions, than seek an open-ended dialogue with them.
Conditions for the existence of religious pluralism
Religious Tolerance
Freedom
of religion encompasses all religions acting within the law in a particular
region, whether or not an individual religion accepts that other religions are
legitimate or that freedom of religious choice and religious plurality in
general are good things.
Exclusivist
religions teach that theirs is the only way to salvation and to religious
truth, and some of them would even argue that it is necessary to suppress the
falsehoods taught by other religions.
Some
Protestant sects argue fiercely against Roman Catholicism, and fundamentalist
Christians of all kinds teach that religious practices like those of paganism
and witchcraft are pernicious.
Many
religious believers believe that religious pluralism should entail not
competition but cooperation, and argue that societal and theological change is
necessary to overcome religious differences between different religions, and
denominational conflicts within the same religion.
For
most religious traditions, this attitude is essentially based on a non-literal
view of one's religious traditions, hence allowing for respect to be engendered
between different traditions on fundamental principles rather than more
marginal issues.
It
is perhaps summarized as an attitude which rejects focus on immaterial
differences, and instead gives respect to those beliefs held in common.
Relativism, the belief that all religions are equal in their value and that
none of the religions gives access to absolute truth, is an extreme form of
inclusivism.
Likewise,
syncretism, the attempt to take over creeds of practices from other religions
or even to blend practices or creeds from different religions into one new
faith is an extreme form of inter-religious dialogue.
Syncretism
must not be confused with ecumenism, the attempt to bring closer and eventually
reunite different denominations of one religion that have a common origin but
were separated by a schism.
The
plurality of religious traditions and cultures has come to characterize every
part of the world today.
But
what is pluralism? Here are four points to begin our thinking:
1. Pluralism is not diversity alone, but the energetic engagement with diversity. Diversity can and has meant the creation of religious ghettoes with little traffic between or among them.
Today,
religious diversity is a given, but pluralism is not a given; it is an
achievement. Mere diversity without real encounter and relationship will yield
increasing tensions in our societies.
2.
Pluralism is not just tolerance, but the
active seeking of understanding across lines of difference. Tolerance is a
necessary public virtue, but it does not require Christians and Muslims,
Hindus, Jews, and ardent secularists to know anything about one another.
Tolerance
is too thin a foundation for a world of religious difference and proximity. It
does nothing to remove our ignorance of one another, and leaves in place the
stereotype, the half-truth, the fears that underlie old patterns of division
and violence.
In
the world in which we live today, our ignorance of one another will be
increasingly costly.
3.
Pluralism is not relativism, but the encounter of commitments. The new paradigm
of pluralism does not require us to leave our identities and our commitments
behind, for pluralism is the encounter of commitments.
It
means holding our deepest differences, even our religious differences, not in
isolation, but in relationship to one another.
With
respect to many, if not most issues, there exist significant differences of
opinion among individuals who seem to be equally knowledgeable and sincere.
Individuals
who apparently have access to the same information and are equally interested
in the truth affirm incompatible perspectives on, for instance, significant
social, political, and economic issues. Such diversity of opinion, though, is
nowhere more evident than in the area of religious thought.
On
almost every religious issue, honest, knowledgeable people hold significantly
diverse, often incompatible beliefs. Religious diversity of this sort can
fruitfully be explored in many ways for instance, from psychological,
anthropological, or historical perspectives.
The
current discussion, however, will concern itself primarily with those key
issues surrounding religious diversity with which philosophers, especially
analytic philosophers of religion, are most concerned at present.
Specifically,
our discussion will focus primarily on the following questions: How pervasive
is religious diversity? Does the reality of this diversity require a response?
Can a person who acknowledges religious diversity remain justified in claiming
just one perspective to be correct?
If
so, is it morally justifiable to attempt to convert others to a different
perspective? Can it justifiably be claimed that only one religion offers a path
into the eternal presence of God? The answers to such questions are not simply
academic. They increasingly have great impact on how we treat others, both
personally and corporately.
With
respect to many, if not most issues, there exist significant differences of
opinion among individuals who seem to be equally knowledgeable and sincere.
Individuals who apparently have access to the same information and are equally
interested in the truth affirm incompatible perspectives on, for instance,
significant social, political, and economic issues. Such diversity of opinion,
though, is nowhere more evident than in the area of religious thought.
On
almost every religious issue, honest, knowledgeable people hold significantly
diverse, often incompatible beliefs.
Religious
diversity of this sort can fruitfully be explored in many ways for instance,
from psychological, anthropological, or historical perspectives.
The current discussion, however, will concern itself primarily with those key issues surrounding religious diversity with which philosophers, especially analytic philosophers of religion, are most concerned at present. Specifically, our discussion will focus primarily on the following questions:
How
pervasive is religious diversity? Does the reality of this diversity require a
response? Can a person who acknowledges religious diversity remain justified in
claiming just one perspective to be correct?
If
so, is it morally justifiable to attempt to convert others to a different
perspective? Can it justifiably be claimed that only one religion offers a path
into the eternal presence of God? The answers to such questions are not simply
academic. They increasingly have great impact on how we treat others, both
personally and corporately.
The Pervasiveness of Religious Diversity
Religious
diversity exists most noticeably at the level of basic theistic systems. For
instance, while within Christianity, Judaism, and Islam it is believed that God
is a personal deity, within Hinayana (Theravada) Buddhism God's existence is
denied and within Hinduism the concept of a personal deity is, in an important
sense, illusory.
Within
many forms of Christianity and Islam, the ultimate goal is subjective
immortality in God's presence, while within Hinayana Buddhism the ultimate goal
is the extinction of the self as a discrete, conscious entity.
However,
significant, widespread diversity also exists within basic theistic systems. For
example, within Christianity, believers differ significantly on the nature of
God.
Some
see God as all controlling, others as self-limiting, and still others as
incapable in principle of unilaterally controlling any aspect of reality. Some
believe God to have infallible knowledge only of all that has occurred or is
occurring, others claim God also has knowledge of all that will actually occur,
while those who believe God possesses middle knowledge add that God knows all
that would actually occur in any possible context.
Some
believe the moral principles stipulated by God for correct human behavior flow
from God's nature and thus that such principles determine God's behavior, while
others believe that God acts in accordance with a different set of moral rules,
that for God what is right is simply whatever God does.
Some
believe that only those who have consciously “given their lives to Christ” will
spend eternity in God's presence. Others believe that many who have never even
heard the name of Jesus will enter God's presence, while others yet do not even
believe subjective immortality (a conscious afterlife) to be a reality.
Muslims
also differ significantly among themselves on these same divine attributes. Or
consider the wide variety of Muslim perspectives on such issues as the autonomy
of the individual when interpreting the Qur'an, how best to apply core Islamic
values to modern life, and the status of women.
While
it is still somewhat popular in philosophical circles today to focus on
diversity among basic theistic systems, there is a growing awareness that the
same basic questions (and responses) that apply to inter-system diversity (for
example, to differing perspectives on the most accurate basic theistic
conception of God) apply just as clearly, and in exactly the same sense, to
intra-system diversity (for example, to differing perspectives within
Christianity over the extent of God's knowledge).
And
there is increasing awareness that the practical import of intra-theistic
diversity is just as significant as is that of inter-theistic diversity.
For
most Christians, for instance, the practical significance of retaining or
modifying beliefs about God's power or knowledge is just as great as retaining
or modifying the belief that Christianity is a better theistic explanatory
hypothesis than is Islam.
Read on: Religious Studies as an Academic Discipline
Possible Responses to Religious Diversity
One
obvious response to religious diversity is to maintain that since there exists
no divine reality since the referent in
all religious truth claims related to the divine is nonexistent all such claims
are false.
Another
possible response, put forth by religious relativists, is that there is no one
truth when considering mutually incompatible religious claims about reality;
more than one of the conflicting sets of specific truth-claims can be correct.
However,
most current discussions of religious diversity presuppose a realist theory of
truth that there is a truth to the matter. When the topic is approached in this
way, philosophers normally center discussions of religious truth claims on
three basic categories: religious exclusivism, religious non exclusivism, and
religious pluralism.
For
the purpose of our discussion, someone is a religious exclusivist with respect
to a given issue when she believes the religious perspective of only one basic
theistic system (for instance, only one of the major world religions) or only
one of the variants within a basic theistic system (for instance, within
Christianity) to be the truth or at least closer to the truth than any other
religious perspective on this issue.
Someone
is a religious non-exclusivist with respect to a given issue when she denies
that the religious perspective of any basic theistic system or variant thereof
is superior to all other religious perspectives on this issue.
And
someone is a religious pluralist with respect to a given issue when she claims
not only (as a non-exclusivist) that no specific religious perspective is
superior but also makes the positive claim that the religious perspectives of
more than one basic theistic system or variant thereof are equally close to the
truth.
Religious Diversity and Justified Belief
What
if we assume, as do most philosophers today, that belief assessment in the face
of religious diversity will not normally resolve debate over conflicting
religious perspectives in an objective manner? That is, what if we assume that
while the consideration of criteria such as self-consistency and
comprehensiveness can rule out certain options, there exists no set of criteria
that will allow us to resolve most religious epistemic disputes (either between
or within religious perspectives) in a neutral, non-question-begging fashion?
In
what epistemic position does this then place the exclusivist? Or to use the
phrasing preferred in the current “epistemology of disagreement” debates, to
what extent, if any, is it reasonable for an exclusivist to retain her
exclusivist beliefs when it is acknowledged that epistemic peers disagree? The
answer, as some see it, is that the exclusivist can no longer justifiably
maintain that her exclusivist beliefs are true. J.C. Schellenberg, for example,
argues that because no more than one among a set of incompatible truth claims
can be true, a disputant in a debate over such claims is justified in
continuing to maintain that her claim is true only if she possesses
non-question-begging justification for believing the incompatible claim of any
competitor to be false.
However,
since no disputant in religious conflicts possesses such justification, no
disputant can be justified “in holding her own claim to be true.” Or, as
Schellenberg states this conclusion in another context, we must conclude that
in the absence of objective, non-question- begging justification, none of the
disputants in religious conflicts “has justification for supposing the others'
claims false”.
David Silver comes to a similar conclusion:
“[Exclusivists] should provide independent evidence for the claim that they
have a special source of religious knowledge … or they should relinquish their
exclusivist religious beliefs” (Silver 2001, 11).
The
proper response for the exclusivist, most in this camp argue, is to suspend
judgment — is for the person who was an exclusivist to abandon her
exclusivistic position and give equal weight to all the self-consistent,
comprehensive perspectives in play (Christiansen, 2009; Feldman, 2007).
Others have not gone this far, arguing rather that while the exclusivist need not abandon religious belief in the face of unresolved conflict, she must or at least will hold her exclusive religious beliefs more tentatively (with less confidence).
Philip Quinn argues, for instance, that acknowledged epistemic
parity necessarily has a negative (epistemically humbling) impact on the level
of justification for any religious belief system.
Such
parity does not necessarily minimize justification below a level sufficient for
rational acceptability. But for those proponents of a religion who are
“sufficiently aware of religious diversity, the justification that the
[religion] receives from its sources is a good deal less than would be the case
were there no such diversity” (Quinn, 2005a, 137).
James
Kraft agrees. When a person acknowledges that those with whom she disagrees are
equivalently informed and capable and have made no obvious mistakes in
reasoning, this person's confidence in her perspective, we are told, is rightly
reduced (Kraft, 2007).
The
tentativeness this reduction in confidence produces, McKim tells us, does not
entail never-ending inquiry. What it means, rather, is that in the face of
unresolved religious diversity, one should be open to the possibility “that one
or more of the [alternatives] may be correct … that the position one had
thought to be correct may be wrong [while] one of the other positions may be
right” (McKim 2001, 154–55). Joseph Runzo and Gary Gutting agree.
According
to Runzo, “all faith commitments must be held with the humbling recognition
that they can be misguided, for our knowledge is never sure” (Runzo 1993, 236).
Gutting
argues that only interim, not decisive assent is justified in the face of
unresolved diversity and that “those who give merely interim assent must
recognize the equal value, as an essential element in the continuing
discussion, of beliefs contrary to theirs” (Gutting 1982, 108).
Moreover,
argues McKim, such tentativeness in the face of diversity has an important
payoff. It can lead to deep tolerance: the allowance “that those with whom you
disagree are people whom it is worthwhile to approach with rational arguments”
(McKim 2001, 178) And personal tolerance of this sort, we are told, may well
lead to a more tolerant and open society that will permit and even encourage a
diversity of opinion on all issues, including opinions on religious matters.
William Alston represents an even more charitable response to exclusivism. His perspective is based on what he sees as a crucial distinction between two types of epistemic disputes: those in which “it is clear what would constitute non-circular grounds for supposing one of the contestants to be superior to the others” and those in which it is not.
In the former case in those cases in
which there is a commonly accepted “procedure for settling disputes” it isn't
clear, he acknowledges, that it is rational for a person to continue to
maintain that her position is superior (Alston 1988, 442–443).
However,
as Alston sees it, there exists no such common ground for settling basic
epistemic disputes over religious truth claims, and this, he contends, alters
the situation drastically. It still remains true, he grants, that the reality
of religious diversity diminishes justification.
But
the fact that “we are at a loss to specify [common ground]” means, he argues,
that with respect to those religious perspectives that are self-consistent, it
is not “irrational for one to remain an exclusivist” — not irrational for the
proponent of any religious perspective to continue to hold that her perspective
is true.
That
is, as Alston sees it, given the absence of common ground for resolving
disputes, the proponent of any self-consistent religious perspective can
justifiably continue to believe this perspective to be true “despite not being
able to show that it is epistemically superior to the competition”.
In
fact, at one point he goes even further. Because there exists at present no
neutral ground for adjudicating religious epistemic conflicts, it is not only
the case, Alston argues, that an exclusivist is justified (rational) in
continuing to consider her own perspective superior.
Since
we do not even know in most cases what a non-circular reason for demonstrating
superiority would look like, the “only rational course” for an exclusivist “is
to sit tight” with the beliefs “which [have] served so well in guiding [her]
activity in the world.”
Or,
to generalize this point, Alston speaks for those who maintain that, given the
absence of common ground for adjudicating disputes concerning self-consistent
religious perspectives, it is not rational for an exclusivist to stop
maintaining that her system is superior (Alston 1988, 444).
Philip
Quinn represents yet another, increasingly popular approach. While he agrees
with Alston that in the face of diversity an exclusivist may well be justified
in continuing to “sit tight” — in continuing to maintain that her religious
perspective is true — he denies that this is the only rational course of action
available (Quinn 2000, 235–246).
The
basis for this position is his distinction between a pre-Kantian and a Kantian
understanding of religious belief.
To have a pre-Kantian understanding of religious belief is to assume that we have (or at least can have) access to the truth as it really is. It is to believe, for instance, that we do (or at least can in principle) know what God is really like.
To have a Kantian understanding of religious belief is to assume that
although there is a literal noumenal reality, our understanding of this reality
(and thus our truth claims about this reality) will of necessity be relative to
the cultural/social/psychological grids through which our conceptualization of
this noumenal reality is processed.
It
is to believe, for instance, that although there is a divine reality about which
we can make truth claims, our understanding of (and thus our truth claims
about) this divine reality will necessarily to some extent be conditioned by
the ways in which our environment (our culture in the broadest sense) has
shaped our categories of thought (Quinn 2000, 241–242).
Alston,
Quinn contends, is essentially working off of a pre-Kantian model of religious
belief when he encourages religious exclusivists to sit tight in the face of
peer conflict since, in the absence of any objective basis for determining
which perspective is right, the exclusivist has no sufficient reason not to do
so.
Quinn
does not deny that this pre-Kantian approach is justifiable and thus does not
deny that someone who follows Alston's advice to sit tight is rational in doing
so.
However, Quinn believes that “it should not be
taken for granted that any of the [contending perspectives] in its present form
is correct.” Hence, he believes it is equally justifiable for an exclusivist to
adopt a Kantian approach to religious belief.
Specifically,
he believes it is equally justifiable for an exclusivist to assume that
whatever any of us can know about the truth of the matter will never be a
description of religious reality that is free of significant “cultural”
conditioning.
Accordingly,
it is also rational, he maintains, for exclusivists encountering diverse truth
claims to “seek a more inclusivist or pluralistic understanding of their own
faith” by modifying their beliefs to bring them “into line with such an
understanding” (Quinn 2000, 242).
In short, as Quinn sees it, those who hold a
position such as Alston's have left us, at least implicitly, with a false
dilemma: either we find common ground on which we can objectively determine
which religious perspective is the truth or we sit tight with what we have.
However,
Quinn holds that, once we realize it is perfectly reasonable for a person to
assume that the proponent of no religious perspective has (or even could have)
an accurate understanding of divine reality as it really is, another rational
alternative appears.
We
then see that it is also perfectly rational for a person to begin to revise her
own phenomenological perspective on the truth in a way that will allow for
greater overlap with the phenomenological perspectives of others. The approach
to conflicting religious perspectives Quinn outlines has in fact become
increasingly popular in exclusivistic circles.
Consider,
for example, the ongoing debate among Christians over how God brought the rest
of reality into existence. Some still claim the Bible clearly teaches that God
created the “heavens and the earth” in six twenty-four hour periods about ten
thousand years ago.
Others
still maintain that the fact that “a day is to the Lord as a thousand years”
means that while God is directly responsible for what the Bible says was
created each “day,” it is most reasonable to believe that the time frame for
each instance of creative activity could well have been millions, or even
billions, of years. And then there are those who still hold that God's direct
creative activity consisted primarily of orchestrating the “Big Bang.”
However,
more recently, many Christians have taken a more Kantian approach. Based on
their assumption that we may well not have access, even though Scripture, to
exactly how God was involved in the creative process, they have modified what
is to be considered essential to Christianity on this issue.
Rather
than affirming any of the specific explanations of how God created all else,
they affirm a more general contention compatible with each of these specific
explanations: that God is in some manner directly responsible for the existence
of all else. They have, in Quinn's terms, thinned their core theologies in a
way that reconciles the divergent perspectives.
Everyone
realizes, though, that moving toward a thinner theology and thicker
phenomenology can resolve the epistemic tension produced by religious diversity
only to a certain extent.
Even
if we assume that it is perfectly reasonable, and possibly even preferable, for
exclusivists to thin their theologies (and thus thicken their phenomenologies)
in an attempt to minimize that core of truths that must be accepted to remain
proponents of the specific theological perspectives in question, to be an exclusivist
even a strongly Kantian exclusivist is still to believe that one's religious
perspective is superior in the sense that it is in some important way closer to
the truth than are the competing perspectives of others.
Accordingly,
while thinning her theology may be a rational choice that can minimize
conflict, no one is arguing that it can be the sole response for an
exclusivist.
At
some point, a person must either cease to be the exclusivist she was or choose
one of the other options: acknowledge that the belief in question isn't true,
hold it more tentatively, or sit tight with what she has.
Finally,
we find at the far end of the spectrum those who deny that acknowledged peer
conflict does in fact require the exclusivist to abandon her exclusivism or
even reduce confidence in her exclusivistic perspectives.
The
key to this position is a distinction between personal (private) evidence and
public evidence (evidence available to all persons involved in the dispute).
It
is granted that an individual will often find herself in epistemic disputes
with persons who are epistemic peers in the sense that they are
(1)
Equally intelligent, thoughtful, and free from obvious bias
(2)
Equally familiar with all the relevant public evidence.
But
the final judgments made by each participant in such disputes are not made
solely on this public evidence, it is held. Such judgments are based also on
personal beliefs to which only each participant has access. Jennifer Lackey
notes, for instance, that each person in an epistemic dispute has greater
access to the reliability of her own belief-forming faculties than do her
epistemic competitors (Lackey, 2010). Ernest Sosa talks of “the gulf between
the private and public domain”.
Peter
van Inwagen speaks of “incommunicable insight that the others, for all their
merits, lack” (van Inwagen, 1996). And the weight of this private evidence, it
is argued, can make it reasonable for an individual to retain her beliefs
(including exclusivistic religious beliefs) with the same level of confidence,
even in the face of acknowledged peer disagreement in the public sense.
Some critics, of course, will maintain that this is primarily a verbal victory. The question, remember, is whether an exclusivist who acknowledges that epistemic peers hold incompatible perspectives can continue to justifiably maintain with full confidence that her perspective is superior.
And
it will seem to some that to claim that participants in epistemic disputes have
access to relevant personal evidence not available to their epistemic
competitors is in fact simply to acknowledge that the dispute is really not
among true epistemic peers in the sense originally intended that is, in the
sense that all parties are assessing the same body of evidence.
Religious Diversity in
Public Education
Public
education in Western culture has always been to some extent a “melting pot.”
But the increasing number of students with non-Western cultural values and
religious traditions is causing public school educators to grapple in new and
sometimes uncomfortable ways with the challenges such diversity poses.
Some
of these challenges are practical — e.g., should Muslim girls be allowed to
wear burkas, should schools designate only Christian religious holy days as school
holidays?
The
focus of this section, however, will be a pedagogical question of increasing
interest in the philosophy of education: How ought the increasing religious
diversity to which students are exposed to affect public school curricula?
(Basinger, 2010).
Most
public school educators agree that increasing student understanding of diverse
religious perspectives is important as this will have positive social outcomes.
It is often argued, for instance, that helping students better understand the
increasing diversity, including religious diversity, they face will better
prepare them to live in a peaceful, productive manner with those with differing
cultural and/or religious values (Kunzman, 2006).
Many
educators, however, want to go further.
It
is also important, they maintain, for students to clarify their feelings about
other religions and their followers. Specifically, they want to foster a more
empathetic understanding of other religious perspectives, an understanding that
encourages students to appreciate the other religions from the perspective of
an adherent of that religion (Kunzman, 2006).
While
few challenge this as a valid goal, there is, though, continuing controversy
over one common method by which educators attempt to engender this type of
empathy in students.
As
some see it, while having students think about diverse religions is an
important step past the mere dissemination of factual information toward
empathetic understanding, having students directly experience these religions
in some way for instance, having students visit a local mosque or having a
representative from a Buddhist Center share with students in a class is also
necessary (or at least very desirable).
However,
while no one denies that these forms of direct experience might broaden a
student's empathetic understanding of a religion, concerns have been raised.
First,
some believe that having students experience a religion, even as “observers,”
can test the limits of the separation of church and state. While the intent of
having students attend a mosque or having a Buddhist talk with students is
seldom to “promote” a religion, the line between “exposure” and intended or
unintended promotion (and even proselytization), they maintain, is a fine one,
especially given the widely varying communication skills and deeply embedded
values and preconceptions of the teacher and/or the representatives of a given
religion to whom students might be exposed.
Second,
there is growing ethical concern that to experience a religion as an observer
might in some cases trivialize or demean the religion in question. Some Native
Americans, for instance, are becoming increasingly concerned with the growing
desire of “outsiders” to seek understanding of their religion(s) by watching or
experiencing sacred ceremonies since such observation, they believe, can
trivialize these ceremonies.
Is
it justifiable for the public school educator to go even further than the
dissemination of accurate information and the attempted engendering of empathetic
understanding?
Specifically,
ought an educator attempt to bring it about that all students affirm a core set
of “appropriate” beliefs about other religions and their adherents? It is
clearly the case that almost all public school educators currently do attempt
to bring it about that students hold certain beliefs related to pervasive human
characteristics, such as race, gender, and disabling conditions.
Students
are encouraged, for instance, to continue to believe, or come to believe, that
engaging in intolerant or discriminatory behavior is wrong and that they should
affirm, or come to affirm, the inherent worth and rights of the disabled, those
of other racial/ethnic backgrounds, etc.
So
if the desire is simply to also encourage students to believe it wrong to treat
those of other religions in intolerant or discriminatory ways and to believe it
right to accept those of other religions as persons with equal inherent value,
few will object.
But
need teachers stop there? Might there not be other beliefs about religions and
their adherents that public school educators can justifiably attempt to bring
it about that all students accept? We can extrapolate from some recent work on
religious diversity by Robert Wuthnow to introduce two beliefs that some might
propose fit into this category.
As
Wuthnow sees it, the most appropriate response to the increasing religious
diversity we face in this country is what he labels “reflective pluralism”
(Wuthnow, 2005: 286-307).
To
engage is this sort of reflection, he tells us, is not simply to become better
informed, or to strive to “live peacefully with those with whom one disagrees”
(be tolerant), or even to attempt to develop an empathetic understanding of
diverse religions.
It
is to engage intentionally and purposefully with “people and groups whose
religious practices are fundamentally different from one's own” (Wuthnow, 2005:
289). And such engagement, as he understands it, includes both
(1)
the recognition that since all of our beliefs, including our religious beliefs,
depend on a point of view “shaped by the culture in which we live,” we should
not regard our “own positions as inherently superior”
(2) “a principled willingness to compromise” in the sense that we must be willing to move out of our social and emotional comfort levels “in order to arrive at a workable relationship with another person” (Wuthnow, 2005: 292).
The benefit of
this form of engagement, we are told, is not only that it can minimize the
likelihood of the sorts of “religious tensions, conflicts, and violence [that]
have been so much a part of human history” (Wuthnow, 2005: 293).
Such
reflective engagement also allows us to focus on “the shared concerns for basic
human dignity” found in the teachings of many of the world's religions, which
can furnish a basis for inter-religious cooperation to combat social ills and
meet basic social needs (Wuthnow, 2005: 294).
It
is important to note that Wuthnow does not explicitly claim or deny that
encouraging students in a public school setting to become reflective pluralists
would be appropriate. But not only does he highlight two increasingly popular
pluralistic claims about religions
(1)
that the beliefs of many religions are equally valid expressions of faith,
expressions that adherents of these religions should be allowed or even
encouraged to maintain.
(2)
that religious believers of all faiths should identify and focus on what these
religions have in common he highlights what such pluralists often note as the
main benefits of widespread affirmation of these beliefs: a reduction in
violent religious conflicts and an increase in socially beneficial
inter-religious cooperation.
And
these outcomes are clearly quite compatible with what we have seen to be a key
reason why public school educators want to increase student understanding of
other religions namely, their desire to better prepare students to live in a
peaceful, productive manner in social contexts that will increasingly be
characterized by religious diversity.
Accordingly, since it seems reasonable to believe that widespread acceptance of the validity of diverse religious perspectives and increased focus on the commonalities in diverse religions might well result in more peaceful, mutually beneficial interaction among followers of diverse religions, the question of whether public school teachers can justifiably attempt to bring it about that students affirm the beliefs in question appears worthy of exploration.
Let's first
consider the contention that many religions contain equally valid expressions
of faith.
Even
if we make the debatable assumption that this is true, it won’t be clear to
many that a public school teacher could justifiably attempt to bring it about
that her or his students believed this to be so.
The
problem is that various religions affirm conflicting doctrinal beliefs on
significant issues. For example, while conservative Christians maintain that
one must affirm certain beliefs about the saving power of Christ to spend
eternity in God's presence, conservative Muslims strongly deny this.
Orthodox
Christians and Muslims are taught not only that the sacred scriptures of other
religions contain false beliefs; they are often encouraged to try to convert
those of other religions to their religious perspective. And while many Muslims
and Christians believe in a personal supernatural creator and personally
immortality, some Buddhists deny both.
This,
however, means that an educator can justifiably attempt to convince students
that all religions are equally valid expressions of faith only if she or he can
justifiably attempt to convince conservative proponents of some of these
religions that some of their core doctrinal beliefs need to be modified or
rejected.
And
to attempt to do this in a public school setting will be seen by many as
violating the prohibition against both restricting the free exercise of
religion and promoting a given religion (Basinger, 2010).
Might
it not, though, at least be justifiable for a public school educator to
encourage students to respect the right of adherents to other religions to
retain their current religious beliefs? If we interpret this as asking whether
an educator can justifiably encourage students not to attempt to prohibit
adherents to other religions from expressing and acting in accordance with
their beliefs, a positive response is noncontroversial since this is only to
say once again that educators should encourage students to be tolerant.
However,
to encourage respect for the religious beliefs of others often carries with it
the explicit or implicit assumption that it is inappropriate, if not unethical,
to attempt to convince adherents of one religion to convert to another.
And
for a public school educator to attempt to convince all students that it is wrong
to proselytize will again be seen by some as placing this educator in the
legally and morally questionable position of attempting to convince some
students to reject or modify what for them is a very fundamental, core
religious belief.
Perhaps, however, there is a different, less controversial option for those educators who want to do more than simply encourage tolerance of expression and empathetic understanding.
Is it not at least justifiable for the public school
teacher to attempt to point out the important common values affirmed by most of
the world's major religions, values that we can all accept and should all
desire to see lived out?
Is
it not justifiable for an educator to point out, for instance, that most of the
world's major religions prohibit such things as killing, lying, stealing, and
sexual exploitation, and that these same religions encourage such things as
helping those in need and treating adherents of other religions with respect.
To do so, it has been argued, would not simply be of value within the classroom or community.
Since religious convictions clearly influence social, political and economic activity on a global scale, emphasizing the shared common values of religions has the potential to facilitate better global relationships.
And to
encourage such relationships is surely an appropriate goal of public education
(Shingleton, 2008).
Conclusion on Religious Pluralism
Some,
of course, will see any focus on “positive commonalities” as yet another thinly
veiled attempt to encourage students to modify their current religious beliefs
in ways that make such beliefs more accommodating of other religious
perspectives.
However,
most see no legal or ethical reason why a teacher should not expose students to
the “positive commonalities” in diverse religious perspectives, and many see
this as a helpful step.
As
we have seen, discussions of religious diversity lend themselves to no easy
answers. The issues are many, the arguments complex, and the responses varied.
It would be hard, though, to overstate the practical significance of this
topic.
While
some (many) issues that philosophers discuss have practical implications for
how we view ourselves and treat others, none is more relevant today than the
question of religious diversity.
Religious
pluralism cannot be ignored in our contemporary global setting. The growth and
universal spread of religious sensitivity are compelling for us to recognize
the most plausible approach to religious dialogue. We have seen that religious
pluralism and diversity require our tolerance and respect of one another.
Religious
diversity is so pervasive that that it cuts across divisions of religions but
it is even found in intra religious affinities. This also affects nearly all
facets of our lives and more especially education.
0 Comments